Alliance
Alliance for the Separation of School & State
1071 N. Fulton St.
Fresno, CA 93728

Home Free
e-letter
State
Rankings
Donation How You
Can Help
Contact
Us
 

"Equality" vs. "Equity"

The incredible diversity of the human being is explored here by George Resch in chapter two of The twelve-year sentence: Radical views of compulsory schooling (ed. William F. Rickenbacker, San Francisco: Open Court Publishing, Inc./Fox & Wilkes, 1998 ? reproduced by permission).

According to Resch, the biological, environmental, cultural and religious differences among us are so vast, they pose special difficulties for standardized democratic public education. Resch points toward the need for a free, pluralistic school system in a pluralistic culture, as the best way to guarantee maximum opportunity for each child.

Chapter two: Human variation and individuality

by H. George Resch

Compulsory schooling is championed in the United States on a number of grounds. Of the reasons usually offered in defense of this policy, the most common seems to be that only by such means will we be able to achieve equality--or equality of opportunity. Our purpose in this paper will be to explore briefly such questions as: "Are individual human beings equal or do they differ in significant ways? Can they be made equal, or at least guaranteed equality of opportunity? Can these goals be reached with the aid of compulsory schooling? What effect does compulsory schooling have?"

"We hold these truths to be self-evident: that all men are created equal. . . . " It is hard to imagine that Thomas Jefferson when writing the American Declaration of Independence had any idea of the far-ranging effect these words would have. Is Jefferson's statement true or is it what Plato called a "noble lie"--a statement, false in fact, but which will, one hopes, lead to beneficial results if generally accepted? Or, how accurate is the statement found in the Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences that "at birth human infants, regardless of their heredity, are as equal as Fords"?1

The first difficulty in approaching the idea of equality is to learn what is meant by the term. This difficulty has been recognized even by many of equality's most ardent champions. Two American authors of a study advocating a closer approach to equality, while calling it a key value on which everyone ought to agree, admit that "unfortunately general equality is almost impossible to define."2 Similarly, in commenting on this difficulty, Professor Daniel J. Boorstin wrote:

Take our concept of equality, which many have called the central American value. No sooner does one describe a subject like this and try to separate it for study, than one finds it diffusing and evaporating into the general atmosphere. "Equality," what does it mean? In the United States it has been taken for a fact and an ideal, a moral imperative and a sociological datum, a legal principle and a social norm.3

Despite its lack of a precise and accepted meaning, this word "equality" continues to be used as an incantation, the mere utterance of which is expected to command assent. As one commentator declared:

Equality is a charmed term. It fascinates reformers. Prophets that wait for signs and portents are almost unanimous in predictions of a widening social equality. When the word can no longer be used indiscriminately, it is still retained as defining an indispensable principle of progress. This and that necessary qualification may be granted; it may be smitten on either cheek with staggering blows, but it is sure to come up sanguine and smiling. It has a charmed life. If it is pushed out the door it comes back through the window. Almost every social theory gets it in somewhere, as a fundamental condition of human welfare. . . . Even when the difficulty in achieving it is recognized, the conviction remains strong that it is desirable, and that effort should constantly be directed toward gaining the little or the much that is attainable--the more the better,--as though there could be no question in a sane mind that inequality is in itself a source of evil.4

The difficulty of pinning down a precise meaning that doesn't fly in the face of reality is hardly surprising. For when we survey the entire animate world, we find nothing remotely resembling equality. On the contrary, one of the most important facts of natural science is the all-pervasive variation to be found in nature. We find this to be the case among plants and animals, but probably such variation reaches its apex in man. Each individual, despite certain apparent similarities, differs from his fellow men in myriad ways. It is well known, for example, that each person bears a unique fingerprint design by which he may be distinguished from millions of his fellow men, and in recent years the work of the renowned biochemist Dr. Roger J. Williams has increasingly shown that similar variations between individuals are to be found throughout the body. Considering the incredible range in size or capacity of bodily organs that is nevertheless considered normal, Dr. Williams stresses that:

Normal individuals are highly distinctive with respect to their stomachs, esophagi, hearts, blood vessels, bloods, thoracic ducts, livers, pelvic colons, sinuses, breathing patterns, muscles and their system of endocrine glands. In all these cases inborn differences are observed which are often far beyond what we see externally.5

This variation is found in perhaps the most marked degree in the human brain. The late Dr. K. S. Lashley, for years the premier researcher in the area of the brain and nerve functions, summarized the status of our knowledge of inheritance and variation of structure in the central nervous system as follows:

The brain is extremely variable in every character that has been subjected to measurement. Its diversities of structure within the species are of the same general character as are the differences between related species or even orders of animals. . . . Discussions of heredity and environment have tended to regard the nervous system, if it is considered at all, as a vaguely remote organ, essentially similar in all individuals and largely molded by experience. Even the limited evidence at hand, however, shows that individuals start life with brains differing enormously in structure; unlike in number, size, and arrangement of neurons as well as in grosser features. The variations in cells and tracts must have functional significance. It is not conceivable that the inferior frontal convolutions of two brains would function in the same way or with equal effectiveness when one contains only half as many cells as the other; that two parietal association areas should be identical in function when the cells of one are mostly minute granules and of the other large pyramids, that the presence of Betz cells in the prefrontal region is without influence on behavior. Such differences are the rule in the limited material that we have studied.6

This information leads Professor Williams to conclude that:

. . . different human brains are as unlike each other as are the brains of different species and even different orders of animals. . . . your brain probably differs from your neighbor's far more than your facial features vary from his. . . . the wide differences in brain structure contribute to make us all spotted with respect to the ease with which we grasp various thoughts, concepts and ideas. This is why we may speak of someone's having a "fine legal mind" or of a person's having a "yen for mathematics" or a student's being a "language whiz." Experts agree that every individual tends to have a pattern of mental abilities or potentialities which is distinctive for him or her alone.7

A considerable amount of work has been done in this area in recent years by Professor J. P. Guilford. He and his colleagues at the Aptitudes Research Project at the University of Southern California have extended the demonstrations of intellectual factorial abilities to a total of approximately a hundred. We have reason to believe that each of the intellectual abilities is distributed in accordance with a Gaussian curve of normal distribution throughout the population. It is also known that individuals vary greatly in terms of the unique patterns of abilities they possess. Unfortunately, the fact that what we call intelligence is composed of a kind of mosaic of these nearly one hundred separate factors is easily obscured by the assignment of a single numerical value to the "I.Q." Thus, while a given individual might have an extraordinary aptitude in one field he might also be significantly deficient in another.

When men vary so greatly in their physical makeup and in the structure of their intelligence it should hardly be surprising that their behavior patterns vary as well. Biologist Garrett Hardin asks:

How can we reasonably expect Mr. A and Mr. B to act like some median stereotype if the thyroid and sex-hormones in the blood stream of one are 10 times as great as in the other? How can we reasonably expect all men to have the same safe-driving records when, even among men with "normal" vision, some are 42 times as good as others in detecting movement in the periphery of the visual field? Is it reasonable to expect the same "philosophy of life" in two men, when the blood stream of one has 10 times as much of the basic energy releasing enzymes as are present in the blood of the other? And how can we reasonably demand that all children partake of a "normal" diet, when the vitamin B1 requirement varies at least four-fold, and the vitamin D requirement at least eight-fold?8

If Jefferson should have known better in 1776 than to have written that "all men are created equal" there is even less reason for contemporary scholars to fall into the same error.9 Jefferson might have been expected to observe around him the widespread inequality, but at that time he was without the scientific explanation for that inequality which was provided by the work of Gregor Mendel and his successors. On the basis of Mendelian law we now know that:

. . . every being conceived by sexual recombination is a genetic accident. Every individual being is thus a pioneer, a biological adventure. No one quite like you can exist in your species. Common heredity may provide a common disposition among contemporaries, or a limited likeness between ancestor and descendant. But the strategy of sex denies the prison of identicality. If you were not created equal, you were yet created free. . . . Sexual recombination imposes diversity on living beings. Evaluated by environment, that diversity becomes inequality.10

No matter in what area we look, then, we find no evidence of equality among men. We find instead the most all-encompassing diversity and inequality. However much men may in some ways seem alike, we find on further examination that this similarity is illusory. The assertion, then, that "all men are created equal" is simply not so. Each has his own unique physical, mental, emotional, and behavioral makeup. We can readily agree, then, with Dr. von Mises when he says that "some surpass their fellow men in health and vigor, in brains and aptitude, in energy and resolution and are therefore better suited to the pursuit of earthly affairs than the rest of mankind."11

This diversity or inequality, far from being a problem to be overcome, is the basis of much of our civilized social order. If all individuals were the same, there would be no division of labor, no trade would take place, and there would seem to be little purpose to any social intercourse. It is the differences between individuals, not their similarities, which provide us with opportunity for personal growth and for an ever-richer social order. As Dr. Rothbard points out:

The development of individual variety tends to be both the cause and the effect of the progress of civilization. As civilization progresses, there is increasing opportunity for the greater development of each person's interests, talents, and reasoning in an expanding number of fields, leading to the growth of his human faculties. And from such opportunities comes the advancement of knowledge which in turn enhances his society's civility. Furthermore, it is the variety of individual interests and talents that permits the growth of specialization and division of labor on which civilized society depends.12

In view of the all-pervasive variation found in nature, and especially among men's aptitudes, abilities, and characters, what can we conclude about the goal of equality? Our only reasonable conclusion is that it is not only an unrealizable goal but that any serious effort to achieve it could only result in the destruction of civilized society. For "if each individual is unique, how else can he be made 'equal' to others than by destroying most of what is human in him and reducing human society to the mindless uniformity of the ant heap?"13

By virtue of both man's variation and his locational diversity, equality not only cannot be achieved but is a conceptually impossible goal for man. And if equality is an impossible goal, any attempt to reach it will be futile, for "if equality is an absurd (and therefore irrational) goal, then any effort to approach equality is correspondingly absurd. If a goal is pointless, then any attempt to attain it is similarly pointless."14

Even when the difficulties and, indeed, the impossibility of social equality become apparent, however, they are seldom sufficient to cause the votaries of equality to abandon their goal. The demand becomes, not equality per se, but "equality of opportunity." Unfortunately, as with its parent idea, its champions seldom specify with any precision what they mean by such a concept. When it is defined at all it is usually done in the most metaphorical terms, "another elastic phrase which means little or much, according to the explanation."15

Most often equality of opportunity is defined in a very loose fashion as a sense of fair play necessary in playing the "game of life." Thus, R. H. Tawney in his Equality says that:

Rightly interpreted, it means, not only that what are commonly regarded as the prizes of life should be open to all, but that none should be subjected to arbitrary penalties. . . . If the rules of the game give a permanent advantage to some of the players, it does not become fair merely because they are scrupulously observed by all who take part in it. When the contrast between the circumstances of different social strata is so profound as today, the argument--if it deserves to be called an argument--which suggests that the income they receive bears a close relation to their personal qualities is obviously illusory.16

And, similarly, Blum and Kalven say that "In terms of the justice of rewards, the point is that no race can be fair unless the contestants start from the same mark."17

And Frank Knight, one of the intellectual founders of the "Chicago School" of economics, also "has repeatedly likened social life to a 'game' or a 'contest,' has talked about the 'distribution of prizes,' has mused on what arrangements tend to make the contest 'interesting to participants and spectators,' and has considered the imposition of 'handicaps.'"18 But here, as with so many analogies, we can be seriously misled when we mistake our theoretical and metaphorical constructs for reality. After all, as Dr. Rothbard has pointed out, "Human life is not some sort of race or game in which each person should start from an identical mark. It is an attempt by each man to be as happy as possible. And each person could not begin from the same point, for the world has not just come into being; it is diverse and infinitely varied in its parts."19

So long as individuals, largely as a result of their biological inheritances, vary so greatly, equality of opportunity is simply not possible. What equality of opportunity can there be, for example, between two young people, one brilliantly intelligent and in vigorous good health and the other a mental dullard with a sickly constitution? Is it not obvious that they are marked for different roles in life and that what they need is unequal opportunities in accord with their unequal endowments?

Even if we were to believe that differences in intelligence and character were the result of differing environments rather than heredity, the difficulties in trying to achieve equal opportunity via equal environments for all would be insurmountable. It seems doubtful that if the full dimensions of such an egalitarian policy were known, many would favor it. Such a policy would "require the abolition of the family since different parents have unequal abilities; it would require the communal rearing of children; the state would have to nationalize all babies and raise them in state nurseries under 'equal' conditions."20 But even such draconian measures as these are necessarily doomed to failure, because the various doctors, nurses and other state functionaries involved in the rearing of these children in nurseries, themselves have unique personalities and abilities. Just as no equality of hereditary endowment is possible, neither is a truly equal environment.

It is the supposed ability of universal compulsory schooling to bring about a society of ever greater equality that has come to be its raison d'être. Only if we take our children at an early age, it is argued, and provide them with an equal opportunity through the common schools can we overcome the legacy of social and economic inequality. Yet there is hardly an area in which egalitarian measures are more certainly doomed to failure than in compulsory schooling.

As we have seen, each child is marked with his own unique personality, with mental and emotional interests and abilities differing from everyone else's. One child may display an extraordinary interest and aptitude in music and yet show no particular promise in a number of other directions. Another child may be highly talented in mathematics and the sciences.

One child may be most suited, in interests and ability, to an extensive course in one subject at a time, another may require a study schedule covering several courses at once and so forth. Given the formal, systematic courses of instruction, there is an infinite variety of pace and course combinations most appropriate for each child.21

This means, of course, that it is precisely those unique qualities of the child that are being developed rather than those qualities he may have in common with others. It means that to the extent that we gear education to the child's own requirements we have education leading not to equality but to inequality, to a greater and greater human differentiation. Human differences and distinctions are thus not eliminated, but heightened and enhanced. In this, education differs markedly from the spirit of democratic equality which, as Everett Dean Martin points out:

. . . strives to ignore the cultural differences among people. Education intensifies them. The attempt to place everyone on the same mediocre plane, even though it be a level considerably above the lowest, is not education; it is a kind of social work. Education means finding ones own level. Like all progress it is qualitative and differentiating. . . . It brings out distinctions of human worth, places people on the rounds of a ladder, the gradations of which are discernible in the kinds of interests they have, in the quality of their choices, the perplexities they wrestle with and overcome, the tasks and issues they set themselves.22

"Ah, yes," the egalitarian may well respond, "what you have said is no doubt true. If we deliberately set out to give everyone a different and unequal education, why, of course we shall end up with highly unequal individuals as a result. We could hardly expect anything else. That is precisely why we want to equalize educational opportunity by schooling all children with a common curriculum in public schools. It is by such a process that we can hope to achieve or at least approach equality."

Even by subjecting all children to the same curriculum, however, we would still be unable to achieve the desired equality. The inborn differences among individuals are too fundamental a part of their natures to be obliterated even by a decade or more of scholastic engineering. Compulsory schooling not only fails to achieve its egalitarian goal, but by subjecting all to the same studies in lockstep fashion effectively denies them any real opportunity at all. The Reverend George Harris points out:

Actual opportunity, which not only invites but constrains youth to appropriate it, is not and cannot be an equal opportunity for all. Behind fifty desks exactly alike fifty boys and girls are seated to recite a lesson prescribed to all. Could opportunity be more nearly alike for half a hundred youth? But the algebra is not an opportunity for the boy who has no turn for mathematics. He may throw his head at the book and stand dazed before the blackboard; but the science is not for him any more than the presidency of the United States is for a tramp--perhaps not so much. Indeed, the more nearly equal the opportunity outwardly, the more unequal it is really. When the same instruction for the same number of hours a day by the same teachers is provided for fifty boys and girls the majority have almost no opportunity at all. The bright scholars are held back by the rate possible to the average, the dull scholars are unable to keep up with the average, and only the middle section have anything like a fair opportunity. Even average scholars are discouraged because the brighter students accomplish their tasks so easily and never take their books home. . . . the prime necessity is inequality of opportunity in agreement with inequality of individuals.23 [Italics supplied]

It is unlikely, then, that compulsory schooling provides any real opportunity for its conscripted subjects at all. Even if we were, however, to assume that some--or even all--were benefited by it, there would still be no reason to believe that this schooling would "necessarily do anything to diminish the inequalities of either economic class or social status distinctions between groups. Whatever the benefits for the odd individuals, schooling heightens the inequalities as it becomes more efficient in monopolizing the selection of winners and losers."24 The effort "comes to grief, in short, because individuals do not all have the same ability to make use of their opportunities with equal or comparable success."25

Probably the most extensive--and certainly the most expensive--demonstration of the elusiveness and ambiguity of the concept "equality of educational opportunity," and the inefficacy of compulsory schooling to bring about such equality, was provided by the recent Coleman Report. Because of its significance it will be worthwhile to examine the genesis and conclusion of the report in some detail.

The report was undertaken in response to section 402 of the Civil Rights Act of 1964:

Sec. 402. The Commissioner shall conduct a survey and make a report to the President and the Congress, within two years of the enactment of this title, concerning the lack of availability of equal educational opportunity for individuals by reason of race, color, religion, or national origin in public educational institutions at all levels in the United States, its territories and possessions, and the District of Columbia..

The study was conducted by Professor James S. Coleman of Johns Hopkins University, aided by a fellow academician and five employees of the U.S. Office of Education. The result was the second longest social science research project ever undertaken. The project involved the testing of 570,000 school pupils and some 60,000 teachers. In addition, information about the facilities available in 4,000 schools was gathered in elaborate detail. The published findings filled a massive volume of 737 pages, accompanied by a supplemental appendix of another 548 pages.26 Its findings, which have been widely reported in both the popular press and in the scholarly journals, have been extremely upsetting to those who have viewed the public schools as the main agency insuring equality of opportunity in the United States. So shattering were the results, in fact, that the study was itself made the subject of a reexamination by a Harvard faculty seminar during the academic year 1966-1967. The results of this seminar were themselves published in a volume of 572 pages--On Equality of Educational Opportunity.27

Even more interesting than the conclusions which emerged from this study, however, was the way the authors and the U.S. Office of Education viewed the idea of equality of opportunity. On the basis the Civil Rights Act of 1964, which authorized the study, it seems patently evident that the legislative viewpoint was that the denial of equal opportunity was occasioned by the inferior facilities and personnel available to Negro and other "minority" students. This interpretation is supported by the use of the term availability, and it is in full harmony with the then prevailing environmentalist concept of equality of opportunity. This interpretation is also shared by Professors Daniel P. Moynihan and Frederick Mosteller who write:

Initially Congress seems to have intended the study to become a tool for legal actions opposing formal discrimination against minority groups. As it became evident that the statute would forbid outright any such discriminatory acts, the final attempt may have been to establish once and for all that gross differences in school facilities did exist, especially as between black and white children in the United States. At all events, the statute implied that there was "lack of availability of equal educational opportunities" and the Office of Education set out to document it.28

The authors place this goal of the Office of Education in perspective by noting that

Equal educational opportunity, defined as desegregated education, had become a central-- perhaps the central--demand of the civil-rights movement by 1950. This strategy in turn led to one of the central Supreme Court decisions of American history, Brown vs. Board of Education of Topeka, which declared, in 1954, that "separate but equal" school facilities were inherently unequal and ultimately ordered the South to desegregate "with all deliberate speed." At the risk of over-simplifying, it may be stated that the central purpose of the EEOS was to support that strategy and hasten that process.29

In the course of the study Coleman and his associates considered five varieties of concepts of equality of educational opportunity.30 Of the five they considered, however, only two were used in the design of the study. The first was the concept that prevailed before the study was undertaken:

Stated briefly, before EEOS, "equality of educational opportunity" was measured in terms of school inputs, including racial mixture. By inputs we mean physical facilities of schools and training of teachers; by racial mixture, the Supreme Court's emphasis on integration.31

If the study had confirmed what the academic establishment and the Office of Education had believed--that the Negro and other designated minorities were denied equality of educational opportunity because of the poorer quality of "inputs" in their schools--is it likely that the prevailing concept would have been abandoned? Is it not more likely that the concept would have been retained in the above form precisely because it had been proven "operationally useful" in proving that these minorities had, in fact, been denied equal opportunities, and that this denial was the obvious reason for their consistently poor performance as measured by standardized tests?

What the Coleman survey did find was that no such significant variance in school inputs as had been imagined to exist was to be found. The survey further found that such variance as was found had little relation to the academic achievement of the students. At this point it may be worth quoting some of Professor Coleman's own summary at length:

Even the school-to-school variation in achievement, though relatively small, is in itself almost wholly due to the social environment provided by the school: the educational backgrounds and aspirations of other students in the school, and the educational backgrounds and attainments of the teachers in the school. Per-pupil expenditures, books in the library, and a host of other facilities and curricular measures show virtually no relation to achievement if the social environment of the school--the educational backgrounds of other students and teachers--is held constant. . . . Altogether, the sources of inequality of educational opportunity appear to lie first in the home itself and the cultural influences immediately surrounding the home; then they lie in the school's ineffectiveness to free achievement from the impact of the home, and in the school's cultural homogeneity which perpetuates the social influences of the home and its environs.32

In terms, then, of the prevailing understanding of what equality of educational opportunity meant, the study should have found that the opportunities enjoyed by the several races were substantially equal, that there had been no significant denial of opportunities "by reason of race, color, religion, or national origins." Instead, the authors, intent upon proving the existence of such deprivation, now changed their conception of equality of educational opportunity to mean equality of school outputs as demonstrated by tests of academic achievement. In other words, so long as all students do not evince equal intelligence by doing equally well in achievement tests we have prima facie evidence of the lack of equal educational opportunity. If one person or one group does less well than another, the cause cannot be some genetic or cultural lack but rather a lack of equal opportunity. And there is the implied responsibility of someone else to make up for the lack. Considering that the Civil Rights Act of 1964 "arose largely out of concern for the status of a specific group: the Negro,"33 perhaps this conclusion is understandable in political terms. In terms of the canons of social science, however, it is a disgrace.

We can readily enough agree with Charles E. Silberman when he says that "the Coleman Report suggests forcibly that the public schools do not--and as now constituted cannot--fulfill what has always been considered to be one of their main purposes and justifications: to ensure equality of opportunity."34So long as individuals vary as they do, there can be no such thing as equality of opportunity. An unequal performance is exactly what we would expect from unequal individuals.


1. H. M. Kallen, "Behaviorism," Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences, Vol. II, p. 498.

2. As quoted in Helmut Schoeck, "Individuality v. Equality" in Essays on Individuality, ed. by Felix Morley (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1958), p. 114.

3. Daniel J. Boorstin, The Genius of American Politics (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1953), p. 176.

"One would think, then, that with so much discussion 'about equality,' there would be little vagueness as to what equality itself is about--what one means by 'equality.' Yet this is not at all the case. I think I can best illustrate this point by recounting a couple of my editorial experiences at the journal, The Public Interest, with which I am associated.

"It is clear that some Americans are profoundly and sincerely agitated by the existing distribution of income in this country, and these same Americans--they are mostly professors, of course--are constantly insisting that a more equal distribution of income is a matter of considerable urgency. Having myself no strong prior opinion as to the 'proper' shape of an income-distribution curve in such a country as the United States, I have written to several of these professors asking them to compose an article that would describe a proper redistribution of American income. In other words, in the knowledge that they are discontented with our present income distribution, and taking them at their word that when they demand 'more equality' they are not talking about an absolute leveling of all incomes, I invited them to give our readers a picture of what a 'fair' distribution of income would be like.

"I have never been able to get that article, and I have come to the conclusion that I never shall get it. In two cases, I was promised such an analysis, but it was never written. In the other cases, no one was able to find the time to devote to it. Despite all the talk 'about equality,' no one seems willing to commit himself to a precise definition from which statesmen and social critics can take their bearings." Irving Kristol, "About Equality," Commentary, Vol. 54, No. 5, (November, 1972), p. 41.

"The issues of schooling, of income, of status have all become matters of social policy because equality has been one of the central values of the American polity. But there has never been a clear-cut meaning to equality, and the earliest form of the idea in the 17th century was quite different from the popular form it assumed in the third decade of the 19th century." Daniel Bell, "On Meritocracy and Equality," The Public Interest, No. 29 (Fall, 1972), p. 39.

4. George Harris, Inequality and Progress (Boston: Houghton Mifflin and Co., 1898), pp. 1-2.

5. Roger J. Williams, You Are Extraordinary (New York: Random House, 1967), p. 35.

6. Ibid., pp. 47-48.

7. Ibid., pp. 48, 50.

8. Garrett Hardin, Nature and Man's Fate (New York: Rinehart & Company, Inc., 1959), p. 188.

9. Noting that the American Declaration of Independence was "drafted without conspicuous circumspection because nothing it said could commit any government to any course of action," Nathaniel Weyl points out that "When he wrote the Declaration of Independence, Jefferson may have had George Mason's Virginia Declaration of Rights before him with its preamble 'of a fundamental nature,' asserting that 'all men are by nature equally free and independent.'

"If Jefferson chose the cruder formulation that 'all men are created equal,' thus asserting a proposition he believed false, the reason probably was that he needed phrases able to move men's souls. His task was to wage psychological warfare, an area in which veracity plays a notoriously subordinate role." Nathaniel Weyl, The Negro in American Civilization (Washington, D.C.: Public Affairs Press, 1960), p. 36. For a discussion of Jefferson's views on human inequality see Weyl, op. cit., pp. 35-51.

"Jefferson's phrase, presented as a self-evident truth, was false . . . and so for almost two centuries American thought, with increasing agony and distortion, has been nailed to a cross of revolutionary propaganda, a passing political slogan which its sophisticated author would have been the last to take seriously. Fundamentalist we may no longer be in our religious contemplations. Yet contemporary social theory can yield nothing to mumbling, illiterate, forgotten multitudes in their cringing devotions to antique creeds." Robert Ardrey, The Social Contract (New York: Atheneum, 1970), p 37.

10. Ardrey, The Social Contract, pp. 35, 37.

11. Ludwig von Mises, "On Equality and Inequality," Modern Age, Vol. 5, No. 2 (Spring, 1961), p. 140.

12. Murray N. Rothbard, Education, Free and Compulsory (Center for Independent Education, undated), p. 5.

13. Murray N. Rothbard, Power and Market (Menlo Park: The Institute for Humane Studies, Inc., 1970), p. 158.

14. Idem.

15. George Harris, op. cit., p. 21.

16. R. H. Tawney, Equality (London: Allen and Unwin, 1931), pp. 129, 143- 144.

17. Blum and Kalven, The Uneasy Case for Progressive Taxation (Chicago: The University of Chicago Press, 1953), p. 85.

18. Leland B. Yeager, "Can a Liberal Be an Egalitarian," in Toward Liberty (Menlo Park: The Institute for Humane Studies, Inc., 1971), Vol. 2, p. 425.

19. Rothbard, Power and Market, p. 159.

20. Idem.

"This is one of the reasons why, again and again, collectivists sneer at the institution of the family. It simply does not tie in with the ideal of equality." Schoeck, loc. cit., p. 123.

"Recently reemphasized by sociologists, the central role of the family in the handing down of social inequality has been recognized since the time of Plato.

"In the Republic, Plato indicated that in the just society it would be necessary to take children away from their parents and have them raised by the state, in order to eliminate the tendency toward inherited social privilege. In the early 19th century, Robert Owen specifically proposed that all children, regardless of the class status of their parents, be educated from childhood in state-supported boarding schools. This suggestion was actually advanced by leaders of the New York Workingmen's party of the 1820s and 1830s. In party documents they argued that since the social environment in families of varying wealth and culture differed greatly, the only chance to insure that the children of the poor had the same chance for success as those of the well-to-do was to send all to public boarding schools. Writing in 1830, these early American radicals, anticipating recent sociological research, held that integrating the children of the rich and the poor in the "common" (integrated) school was not enough. For they argued that the most important part of education goes on outside the classroom:

For our part, we understand education to mean everything which influences directly or indirectly the child's character. To see his companions smoke segars is a part of his education; to hear oaths is a part of his education; to see and laugh at drunken men in the streets is a part of his education. And if any one thinks that an education like this (which is daily obtained in the streets of our city) will be counteracted and neutralized by half a dozen hours of daily schooling, we are not of his opinion. . . .

Is not the development of social habits, of the dispositions, of the moral feelings, of the most important of the teacher's duties? And what opportunity of fulfilling them, unless the pupil be at all times under his very eye and control?

We conceive, then, that State Schools, to be republican, efficient, and acceptable to all, must receive the children, not six hours a day but altogether; must feed them, clothe them, lodge them, must direct not their studies only, but their occupations and amusements; must care for them until their education is completed, and then abandon them to the world as useful, intelligent, virtuous citizens.

We do not consider the question regarding day schools and boarding schools as a non-essential matter that can be decided either way without ruin to the cause. On its decision depends whether the system of education which the people call for, shall be a paltry palliative or an efficient cure; whether aristocracy shall be perpetuated or destroyed; whether the poor man's child shall be educated or not; whether the next generation shall obtain their just rights or lose them.

"There are few reformers today who would be prepared to make a suggestion as radical as this one. Perhaps even more than the taking away of children from their parents, the kind of all pervasive moral supervision called for by the New York Workingmen probably seems repugnant even to today's most committed egalitarians. But it is necessary to raise the question of whether these radicals of the 1830s did not see the issue more clearly and reason about it more consistently than many radicals of the 1970s. For if one really wishes a society in which there is not merely formal equality of opportunity but where class background has absolutely no relation to success, one must be willing to pay the necessary price. And that price would appear to include the practical abolition of the family, the suppression of varying cultural and ethnic influences, and a vigorously imposed uniformity in the education of the young. As the Communist experience has shown, the abolition of capitalism, at least in itself, is by no means sufficient." Seymour Martin Lipset, "Social Mobility and Equal Opportunity," The Public Interest, No. 29 (Fall, 1972), pp. 106-108.

21. Rothbard, Education, Free and Compulsory, p. 6.

22. Everett Dean Martin, The Meaning of a Liberal Education (Garden City, N.Y.: Garden City Publishing Company, Inc., 1926), pp. 112-113.

23. Harris, op. cit. pp. 43-46.

24. Colin Greer, Cobweb Attitudes (New York: Teachers College Press, Columbia University, 1970), p. 29.

25. Helmut Schoeck, Envy (New York: Harcourt, Brace & World, Inc. 1969), p. 243.

"What is at stake today is the redefinition of equality. A principle which was the weapon for changing a vast social system, the principle of equality of opportunity, is now seen as leading to a new hierarchy, and the current demand is that the 'just precedence' of society, in Locke's phrase, requires the reduction of all inequality, or the creation of equality of result--in income, status, and power--for all men in society. This is the central value problem of the post-industrial society." Daniel Bell, "On Meritocracy and Equality," The Public Interest, No. 29 (Fall, 1972), p. 40.

26. James S. Coleman, Ernest A. Campbell, Carol J. Hobson, James McPartland, Alexander N. Mood, Frederic D. Wainfield, Robert L. York, Equality of Educational Opportunity, 2 volumes (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing Office, 1966) Superintendent of Documents Catalog No. FS 5.238: 38001.

27. Frederick Mosteller and Daniel P. Moynihan, editors, On Equality of Educational Opportunity (New York: Vintage Books, a Division of Random House, 1972).

28. Mosteller and Moynihan, "A Pathbreaking Report," Ibid., p. 5.

"The Office of Education, which sponsored the research, and Coleman himself had expected to find gross inequality of educational resources between black and white schools and to use these findings as an argument for large scale federal spending to redress the balance." Daniel Bell, "On Meritocracy and Equality," The Public Interest, No. 29, (Fall, 1972), p. 44.

29. Ibid., pp. 29-30.

30. James S. Coleman, "The Evaluation of Equality of Educational Opportunity," in Mosteller and Moynihan, op. cit., p. 147. See also Coleman, "The Concept of Equality of Educational Opportunity," Harvard Educational Review, 38, Winter 1968, pp. 7-22; Edmund W. Gordon, "Toward Defining Equality of Educational Opportunity," and Henry S. Dyer, "The Measurement of Educational Opportunity," in Mosteller and Moynihan, op. cit., pp. 423-436, 513-527.

31. Mosteller and Moynihan, "A Pathbreaking Report," op. cit., p. 6.

32. As quoted in Mosteller and Moynihan, "A Pathbreaking Report," op. cit., p. 20.

33. Ibid., p. 30.

34. Charles E. Silberman, "A Devastating Report on U.S. Education," Fortune, August 1967, p. 181, quoted in Mosteller and Moynihan, "A Pathbreaking Report," op. cit., p. 30.

[top]